I don't doubt you when you say that five dollars is all you can
offer. But have you ever thought that there may be other ways of
remunerating a writer than by giving cash?
--- Henry Miller Open Letter to Small Magazines
How
is writing influenced by legal systems and the institutions that
protect their activity?
Recent studies1 have examined and discussed in depth the
relationship between legal systems and the birth of the concept of
the author in various national and cultural contexts. One of the
points that has been focused on in these researches is the idea
that, as Martha Woodmansee has put it, "one of the most powerful
vehicles of the modern authorship construct was provided by the laws
which regulate our writing practices".2 If we look at the history of
the laws which regulate writing practices, we find two fundamental
systems that follow each other. The first is "publishing privilege",
and then, from the middle of the 1700's in England, "intellectual
property".
Here an attempt will be made to draw out the significance of the
move from the first system to the second, investigating certain
consequences and repercussions.
This paper is divided into four parts. The first part provides a
brief discussion of the current intellectual property system with
particular regard to the way in which this is interpreted by
economic theory. The second part shows, according to certain
essential lines, the system of printing privilege in Europe between
the 15th and 18th centuries. It seeks, in particular, to reveal the
ratio of this system and its justification. The third part examines
the foundation of authorship in Kantian thought. It discusses the
particular link that is established between this concept and the
phenomenon of human freedom. The fourth and final part examines some
possible incongruities in the current intellectual property-system -
incongruities that are noticeable and visible precisely because of
the background of the previous privilege-system and the Kantian
foundation of authorship.
I.
Our way of relating to books, and more generally to the writings
of both past and contemporary authors, is based on certain more or
less explicit assumptions. The first of these is that books
themselves are fundamentally a particular category of "product".
They differ from other industrial or manual production because they
are creative works. The second assumption is that the only real and
legitimate individual responsible for the realisation of a creative
work is the author. The third assumption follows from the second, by
arguing that the author is also the only real and legitimate owner
of the work that he has created. Finally, as the owner of the work
created by himself, the author should have the right to make free
use of his ownership. This means that he should be free to sell it
in whole or part, and that he possesses as well as "moral" rights
over the work (personal and thus inalienable rights), material
rights as well.
Taken together, these assumptions influence our relationship with
writing practices (both our own and those of others). They provide a
sort of "paradigm", namely - to use the terms employed by Thomas
Kuhn3 - a durable and relatively flexible system of shared
assumptions. For the sake of simplicity we will indicate this
paradigm with the name of its most representative legal institution,
that is to say: intellectual property-system.4
The idea of intellectual property did not always exist. The
assumptions behind it that we have briefly recalled (creativity,
authorship, free use, ownership), are not universal and timeless
concepts. They are the result of a relatively recent, profound and
unprecedented change in the way that people have traditionally
related to works of art and thought. This is a "revolution" that we
are perhaps still a long way away from completely understanding in
all its meaning.
Before trying to describe some of the elements of this
"revolution" we should consider one of its consequences. We have
said that the author, as the legitimate and unique owner of the work
created by him, can make what use of it he thinks best. Although he
can never renounce his authorship of a work, he remains free to
grant in whole or in part his ownership of the work. In this way the
creative work becomes an exchangeable good. It becomes, in the full
economic sense of the word, a commodity. The relationship between
the writer and society thus takes the particular form of an
exchange. It is an exchange in which the commodity that is exchanged
is not just a product, but the creative product of an author who
freely sells his own property.
From the 1850's onwards, when the fundamental concepts of the
intellectual property system took shape in the laws and legal
institutions of different countries, the traditional legal doctrine
progressively moved towards the concepts and language of political
economy.5 From the point of view of economic theory, the presence of
laws that protect intellectual property is justified on the grounds
of the particular nature of these goods that are "works of the
mind". In defining this nature the economists of the first half of
the 1800's sometimes talk about "immaterial products".6 The central
point, that was well explained by Léon Walras in an article in
1890,7 is that the so-called fruits of human ingenuity - artistic,
scientific or industrial ideas - can certainly be considered as
"useful goods" like the products of industry or manual labour; they
lack, however, an essential condition that makes a useful good
capable of being an object of exchange. This lack is the
impossibility of making them available in a limited quantity. In
economics, the limited quantity of a useful good is called
"scarcity". There can only be a demand for the purchase of
relatively scarce useful goods, as no one would ask to purchase
items that are freely limitless such as air or sunshine. As a
result, only scarce useful goods can be privately owned. The
characteristic of ideas, however, is that they are never
economically scarce. Once they become public, they are available to
everyone and can be shared by everyone without losing any of their
value. Anyone who wishes to do so can benefit from them freely,
unless some authority does not intervene to make them artificially
scarce, "making a naturally free item into an artificial monopoly".8
The law that protects intellectual property arranges things so that
ideas and works of intellect become exchangeable and can pass from
hand to hand not freely and without limit, but on the basis of an
economic exchange relationship. In other words, it is a specific act
of authority that adds an "exchange value" to the "value of use"
that these goods have.9
A first indication becomes clear from what has been said: ideas,
and specifically the works of ingenuity, are not naturally
commodities, but that they are nonetheless treated as if they were
commodities. This "as if", this "fiction" has to be guaranteed by an
authority that remains above the individual actors of the economic
exchange. No natural market law (any "unseen hand") is capable of
producing this fiction by itself. The fiction must be established as
such.10 From the economic viewpoint, ignoring for the moment the
other, albeit important elements, the intellectual property-system
is a way of establishing the exchangeability of ideas, and thus a
way of giving life to the fiction according to which these are full
commodities like other goods.
Acknowledging that such a fiction is to some degree necessary, we
ask however: is what we have called the "intellectual
property-system" the only possible way of establishing it?
II.
From
the period of the invention and diffusion of printing - at the end
of the 1400's - there was a long pause until the middle of the
1700's before the assumption began to take shape that the work of
the mind should be considered in all effects the "property" of its
"author". It was only around the middle of the 1800's that this
assumption, along with the other ones related to it that we have
described above, was translated into a stable legal and
institutional framework. If we have to give a name to the way in
which, before the invention of intellectual property, the
exchangeability of intellectual work was established and maintained,
we could refer to book privilege.
The book-privileges are usually seen as the forerunners of
intellectual property, and are thus regarded as primitive legal
instruments that were after all inadequate to represent the real
"rights" of the author. Their inadequacy would consist in the fact
that the privilege (priva lex = law-exempt) remained a favour, a
concession of the sovereign, almost the recognition of a status
outside or above the law. They were not based on the principle that
ideas are the property of the individual just like all the other
outcomes of his labour. On the occasion of the first meeting of the
international association of writers (1878), Victor Hugo, addressing
legislators warned that "literary property is in the right, and it
is up to you now to bring it in the laws".11 Conversely, privilege
is not just outside the law, but is an explicit exception to law in
favour of an individual or category of individuals.
However, if we examine the privilege system in itself rather than
starting from principles and notions that will take the form of
acquired wealth only in the intellectual property system, the
privilege system can have a different appearance. It might seem not
just an "imperfect approximation" to the intellectual property
system, but a rational and successful way to make the work of the
mind an exchangeable good.
Let us thus endeavour to understand the reasoning of the privilege
system without being influenced by assumptions and concepts that
emerged later.
The book-privilege is, in some respects, similar to patenting
rights for new inventions. The strict separation, in the sphere of
intellectual property, between "copyright paradigm" and "patent
paradigm", only came about in the second half of the 1800's.12 In
Flaubert's celebrated novel Madame Bovary, 1857, monsieur Homais
raises a toast to "industry and the fine arts, those two sisters!"
It is no coincidence that the distinction between "invention" and
"creation" - a distinction upon which is implicitly founded the
subdivision of intellectual property into copyright- and
patent-paradigm - was not made in European languages before the
middle of the 1800's. As late as 1850, Alessandro Manzoni entitled
Dell'invenzione [On Invention] a treatise on the essence of artistic
and literary work.13 Up to the 18th century, the sphere of invention
was ample enough to include what we nowadays attribute to aesthetic
creation.14 Thus, the book-privilege is not different, from the
juridical point of view, from a privilege granted, for instance, to
exploit mineral resources or to the invention of a new loom.
We come to the same conclusion if, instead of looking to the
object of the privilege, we examine the reasons for the request and
granting of the privilege. Apart from contingent motives that might
encourage a sovereign to grant a privilege, the fundamental reason
for the granting of privilege seems to be the need to protect an
economic interest. The economic considerations were frequently
explicitly mentioned in both the requests and the privileges
themselves, while considerations of other kinds (social utility,
literary excellence, entertainment value, etc.) appear more
rarely.15 Since only few books had a pre-eminent economic interest,
the institution of privilege was designed almost exclusively for a
restricted category of library production. Of all the books
published in Paris in the first quarter of the 1500's, only 5% or a
few more contain on the frontispiece the words "cum privilegio".16 A
similar calculation carried out on Venetian publications for the
period 1741 to 1757 shows that privileged books amounted to 20% of
the total.17 The use of privilege was thus increased but always
involved a small number of publications, and precisely those with a
striking commercial character. In the same way, in England, at least
until the end of the 1600's, privileges regarded almost exclusively
"classes of books such as lawbooks, catechisms, Bibles, ABCs and
almanacs",18 in other words books which represented a considerable
investment by printers and were at risk from pirate editions. Still
in the 1700's, privilege was an exceptional fact in the kingdom of
Savoy, and only regarded editions that were of certain success such
as almanacs and scholastic editions. 19
The fact that privilege was designed as an instrument that
responded to an economic need finds indirect confirmation in the
difference in the duration of one privilege and another. Although
there is no absolute evidence in this regard, it is certain that, in
deciding the duration of the privilege, the authorities above all
took account of the need to maintain a certain proportion with the
scale of the investment made. It is known that, mostly in the
initial period of the diffusion of printing, a longer privilege was
usually granted to books that required a large investment (such as
dictionaries and illustrated books).20 Later on, when the method of
granting privileges and their duration had become standardised, this
institution was also used as an instrument for redistributing
resources among members of the guild. In Venice, for example, a rule
of 1765 established that "common books", those that were not
privileged or books whose privilege had expired, would be assigned
to "needy printers" as a form of "compensatory monopoly for losses
suffered".21
Another consideration has to be made about the subjects of
privileges. From the beginning the custom was to grant privileges
not just to printers but also directly to the author(s) or editor(s)
of the work. It would be however mistaken to see in this practice an
advance of "author's right" in the sense of the current intellectual
property system. The author was regarded not as the individual
responsible for creative production, but as an individual with a
specific interest (economic and otherwise) that had to be
safeguarded. The author was protected uniquely owing to the expenses
and troubles he had undertaken, and not because the book was his
"legitimate property". It is no surprise that, in their requests to
sovereigns, authors always emphasised the exceptional investment (in
terms of time, money and labours) that the work had caused.
According to John Feather, privileges granted directly to authors in
pre-Revolutionary England concerned books that "almost without
exception […] were learned works that had involved their authors in
long periods of compilation, and sometimes great expense".22 In the
1700's the author's privileges granted in the kingdom of Savoy
"concern a still restricted number of works" made up of demanding
works such as "dictionaries, translations of the Latin and Greek
Classics, maps, etc.".23 Sometimes the privilege was granted for
reasons of prestige or to emphasise the particular value of a work.
The celebrated papal privilege obtained by Ludovico Ariosto in 1516
for the first Ferrara edition of his Orlando furioso is a case in
point. As Mark Rose comments, there were many other episodes where
"the actions of [the authorities] are best understood in terms of
"honour" and "reward" rather than "property".24
The conditions included in the privileges relate above all to
economic considerations. The commonest condition concerns the sale
price of the book which must not exceed a given sum, while on other
occasions a general condition was included that the book had to be
sold justo pretio, "at a fair price". In Venice, in 1554, the
granting of the privilege included an estimate that, among other
things, had to establish the sale price.25
Concerning the authorities which granted privileges, it can be
said that every acknowledged power could manage their granting and
observance. We find, thus, a plurality of "sources" that reflect the
organisation of powers in the States of the ancien régime. In
France, alongside royal patents, we find a series of privileges
accorded by parliament, by other sovereign courts (such as the Cour
des Aides or the Grands Jours) and provincial parliaments as well as
ecclesiastical hierarchies (religious orders, bishops) and academies
(schools, universities).26 In Venice, before the system was reformed
in 1603, privileges were granted equally by the Senato and by the
Consiglio.27 The situation in Germany was clearly more complex, and
privileges were granted by a multiplicity of authorities, ranging
from the Emperor to the Reichsregiment, as well as princes, dukes,
and the Senates of different cities.28 To all these privileges,
which had validity over a more or less extensive territory, are to
be added papal privileges, which incorporated an implicit moral
dissuasion or even the explicit threat of excommunication of
transgressors. Papal privileges, and in a different sense imperial
ones, could be regarded as almost "supranational" acts on the
grounds of their moral value which was universally recognised.29
We cannot conclude this brief reconstruction of the privilege
system without considering the market structure in which book
privileges operated. We have already recalled that only a few books
were protected by privilege. But there were also differences among
the books that did receive protection, and this depended on the type
of privilege obtained. One can reasonably suppose that beneath these
differences there was a plurality of "circuits" that were more or
less connected with each other, and that each category of book was
exchanged within a specific circuit. We can above all hypothesise a
"vertical" difference. There were books whose diffusion was
predominantly or exclusively in local markets. Then there were books
which circulated within the boundaries of a national language (which
did not necessarily coincide with state boundaries).30 Finally,
there were books destined for a refined and polyglot readership:
these were often written in Latin and their market extended
virtually over the whole civilised world. It was only as regards the
final group that it was worthwhile requesting a papal or imperial
privilege. Other books had less protection if any at all. In the
ambit of the "high" circuit, i.e. the international market, there
were as well unwritten rules and customs that provided good
protection against pirate editions. Febvre and Martin remark, with
reference to the international book trade in the 1500's and 1600's
that "bookmakers had no interest in competing against each other. In
an epoch when every large publisher had business with foreign
counterparts, the ruin of one would risk the ruin of many others.
Every bookmaker, every city had its own 'assortment' that commercial
correctness and the interest of all involved, would usually impede
to imitate".31 As well as this "vertical" difference we also
discover a "horizontal" difference, or rather a plurality of
circuits that corresponded to different genres and purposes of
books. Thus, for religious books it could be useful to obtain an
ecclesiastical privilege. This could be granted not just by the
papacy but also by the bishop or even a religious order.32 Legal,
medical and scientific texts which generally circulated in the
universities could receive privileges directly from the academic
authorities.
The book market in the privilege system thus seems like a group of
circuits operating independently of each other, each of which had
its own rules and purposes with no common denominator. Privilege is
a method for establishing the exchangeability of the book-commodity
as a function of the market in which this commodity was exchanged
(i.e. bought and sold). A book's exchange value, which the privilege
creates with a free institutional act, remains determined and
defined not just within tempo-spatial limits, but "moral" ones also.
The book is not purely and simply "a commodity": it is a commodity
as well as serving the needs of a buying-selling exchange. Where
there is no economic interest, or where economic interest has
already been met, and thus where there are no longer buyer-seller
relationships, no exchange value needs to be ascribed to the book. A
book outside a buyer-seller relationship, and thus outside a
commercial circuit, no longer needs to be conceived as a
commodity.33
III.
On one side the privilege system is an alternative method to that
of the intellectual property system for establishing the
exchangeability of works of the mind. On the other side it is a
practice, or series of practices, within which exchangeability is
not extended indefinitely but is maintained within certain limits.
The questions we now have to raise are: what are these limits? To
what extent can a book be considered a commodity? And how can one
determine, within these limits, the figure of the author and of
authorship?
We will respond to these questions by following in the tracks of a
writer who, from the chronological point of view, is found on the
borders of the two "paradigms" that we have called privilege and the
intellectual property system. This thinker is Immanuel Kant.
In his Metaphysical Principles of the Science of Right, 1797, Kant
attempts to deduce the illegitimacy of counterfeiting books by
starting with the question "What is a book?"
A book is a writing which represents a discourse addressed by some
one to the public, through visible signs of speech. […] He who
speaks to the public in his own name is called the author (auctor);
he who addresses the writing to the public in the name of the author
is the publisher. […] The publisher, again, speaks, by the aid of
the printer as his workman (operarius), yet not in his own name, for
otherwise he would be himself the author, but in the name of the
author; and he is only entitled to do so in virtue of a mandate
(mandatum) given him to that effect by the author.34
The book brings together a set of relationships. Firstly, between
the author and the public; then, between the author and the
publisher and between the publisher and the public; finally, there
is a relationship between the publisher and the printer. The first
of these relationships is one "of his words" - the author speaks to
the public. The second (author-publisher) is, on the other hand, a
contract, and specifically a contract based on a mandate. The third
relationship (publisher-public) is also a relationship "of his
words" like the first, but in this case the words are not those of
the publisher. The publisher limits his actions to administering,
"conducting the negotiation between the author and the public",35
and enjoying all the advantages that he legitimately can from this
negotiation. Among these advantages, although Kant does not mention
them specifically, is included the sale of the book. The final
relationship is between the publisher and the printer, and this is a
contract of work done.
Before proceeding, one thing is worth noting in Kant's
formulation. These relationships are not simply placed alongside
each other at the same level. There is a "prioritary" relationship
which underlies and regulates all the others, i.e. which gives rise
to a series of "derived" relationships. The principal relationship
is that between the author and the public. This takes the form of
the relationship between the author and the publisher and the
publisher and the public, and this in turn gives rise to the
relationship between the publisher and the printer. This subdivision
of relationships is not random - each of the "derived" relationships
corresponds to a precise contractual figure.36
To settle these contractual figures, Kant relies explicitly on the
tradition of Roman law. As far as the institutions that regulate
working relationships among individuals are concerned, we find in
Roman law a difference between the contract of work done (locatio
operarum) and the contract of attorney or mandate (mandatum). Thus,
there is a strict distinction between these two contracts on one
side and the contract of purchase and sale (emptio-venditio) on the
other.37 It is only the purchase-and-sale contract that contains the
price equivalent (pretium). In a contract for work done, given that
the thing (res) exchanged is not a piece of work (opus) but one's
own work (opera), the contract does not contain the payment of an
equivalent price but a straightforward wage (merces) for the work
performed. On the contrary, the mandate is a perfect contract in
itself which is based on the trust (fides) of the two counterparts,
and thus has no need to conclude with an act of payment. The
contract may - but does not have - to be followed by a grateful
reward in the form of an honorarium. The main characteristics of the
honorarium compared to all other forms of payment (such as the
pretium and the merces) are as follows: 1. It is not obligatory; 2.
There is no a priori relationship of equivalence with the work
provided by the mandatary or the task entrusted by the mandator.38
What Kant argues in the passage quoted is that the author is not a
performer of work (including intellectual work) nor a seller (of his
own manuscript). The relationship between the author and the
publisher is maintained within the precise limits of the mandate,
with all the results that derive from this legal figure. One of
these consequences is illustrated in the article On the Unlawfulness
of Counterfeiting Books, 1785:
[The publisher] possesses the manuscript only on the condition to
use it for the purpose of a deal of the author with the public; but
this obligation towards the public remains, though that towards the
author has ceased by his death. Here [the argument] is not built
upon a right of the public to the manuscript, but upon a right of
the public to a deal with the author. Should the publisher give out
the author's work, after his death, mutilated or falsified, or let
the necessary number of copies for the demand be wanting; the public
would thus be entitled to force him to more justness or to augment
the publication, but otherwise to provide for this elsewhere. All of
which could not take place, were the publisher's right not deduced
from a deal that he transacts between the author and the public in
the name of the former.39
If, then, the book is founded on a deal between the author and the
public, what is the ultimate purpose and reason for this deal?
In Kant's view, the book has, as far as thought is concerned, a
similar function to that of money in the commercial world. As money
is "the universal means through which men exchange the products of
their work with each other",40 the book is the pre-eminent means for
men to communicate and exchange what they think. The peculiarity of
the book, its essential characteristic, is thus the fact that it is
the "medium for the exercise and circulation of thought".41 The
similarity with money stops here, however. The relationship between
thought and its communication is not something extrinsic like that
between commodities and their circulation. A commodity remains a
commodity even when it lies unemployed in a warehouse, while thought
- unlike what is commonly assumed - cannot be thought in the absence
of communication. That's what Kant propounds in an essay of 1786
called What Does It Mean: to Orient Oneself in Thought?:
It is often said that a superior power can deprive ourselves of
the freedom to speak or to write, but not of the freedom to think.
But how much and how correctly we would think, if we won't think so
to say 'in common' with others, to whom we communicate our thoughts
and who communicate us theirs? Thus one can really say that the
power that removes men's freedom to communicate their thoughts
publicly, also deprives them of their freedom to think, that is the
only treasure left us in the midst of social impositions, the only
means which can still permit us to find remedies for the ills of
this condition.42
A power that limits the freedom of communication also prejudices
the possibility itself of thought. It is frequently thought that
thinking is a solitary activity, a sort of individual performance
that can remain confined to the individual or may be shared with
others at a later date. At most we can imagine a "collective work",
meaning that the thought may result from the combined efforts of
more individuals. What we cannot see, is that thought is precisely
the element that, so to say, "de-individualises" the individual,
bringing into play something greater than the individual itself.
Thinking puts man immediately in relationship with something other,
which is not merely the dimension of "other individuals". Kant wants
to draw our attention to the fact that thought is, in itself,
"communication" in a high sense. To be aware of this it is enough to
consider what thinking really means. In line with tradition, Kant
understands thought as essentially judging.43 Judgement is certainly
an operation that involves each individual. But precisely in
judging, that is in connecting a "predicate" with a "subject" in a
proposition, every individual relies on something other - in the
matter in hand: to what regards which is accomplished the
connection. In Kantian terms, every judgement is based on "the
necessary unity" in view of which the judgement is carried out.44 In
this sense, precisely in the individual act of judgement the
individual is already de-individualised - he is already beyond
himself and heading towards something other. The most immediate form
of this "being-by-otherness" is being with other human beings. This
is why it is so necessary to have one's own thoughts (judgements)
tested by other thinking (judging) beings. Denying or undervaluing
the importance of this comparison is for Kant a shifty form of
absence of thought, a sort of egoism. In his Anthropology from the
Pragmatic Viewpoint he uses the term "logical egoism" to distinguish
this from the commoner form of "moral" one:
The
logical egoist considers it superfluous to subject his own thought
to another intellect, as if he had no need for this comparison
(criterium veritatis externum). But it is so certain that we cannot
give up this means to assure ourselves of the correctness of our own
judgement, that this is perhaps the principal reason why learned
people fight so hard for the freedom of the press. If this freedom
is denied, we would thereby lose a very potent means for proving the
correctness of our own judgements and we would be left to error.45
No
form of thought, including pure mathematics, can give up this means
of testing its own judgements.46 And because this means can be
fruitfully deployed, it is necessary that "the best means for the
circulation of thought" are left free. The freedom of the press is
thus only a means for guaranteeing a much more fundamental freedom,
that is the freedom from error. Here Kant is once again a faithful
interpreter of tradition:47 humanity can only be free in the truth,
and the freedom of the press is only a formal condition of the full
and complete liberty of man.
It is not possible here, as would be necessary, to go deeper into
the Kantian idea of freedom. It will suffice to observe that, for
Kant, freedom, because it is a faculty that "belongs to the activity
of all rational beings endowed with a will",48 cannot be showed and
demonstrated on the ground of experience. All experience is possible
only because we are free. Consequently, "every being that cannot act
except under the idea of freedom is just for that reason in a
practical point of view really free".49 Thus freedom is the element
in which each free experience of man takes place. It is in this
freedom that the basis of the relationship between the author and
the public is found, a relationship on which all the other
relationships remain subordinate, each of which has a precise
contractual shape.
IV.
In Kantian thought, the author is not only the "owner" of the
"work", but is above all responsible for a discourse, that is a
thought explicitly offered to be shared with other human beings in
order to weigh and test together its own truth. In its turn, the
"public", as beneficiary of the author's discourse, is not simply a
set of consumers of a good, but is the ambit in which the judgements
can be placed for testing, and is thus the ambit in which the
possibility of being in the truth is preserved. Consistent with
Kant's position are the following words of Vittorio Alfieri, who
writes in his clear-sighted treatise Il principe e le lettere [The
Prince and Letters], 1789: "Reading, as I intend it, means
profoundly thinking; thinking means hold on and hold on, it means to
endure".50 The public is then a set of readers in the full sense of
the word. Readers are not merely "consumers of books" but thinking
beings, that is willing to endure and share the author's search for
the truth. It is in only in this willingness to endure that the
ultimate justification for the Kantian "right of the public to deal
with the author" finds itself.
On the basis of these considerations we can now turn to the
question with which we started: to what extent are writing practices
influenced by the legal systems and institutions that protect their
activity? After what we have seen, we can formulate the question in
the following terms: Is there a substantial difference in the author
and public relationship in the privilege and intellectual property
systems?
Before attempting to answer this question, it is worthwhile
briefly reviewing the points made so far.
We started with a definition of the intellectual property system
as a way of establishing the exchangeability of ideas through the
recognition of a right of author's ownership. We then considered, as
an alternative method for establishing this exchangeability, the
privilege system that was used in European States until the 18th
century. The main feature of privilege is the fact that it regards
exclusively economic relationships in production and exchange, and
has no significance outside these relationships. As a result, the
establishment of the exchangeability of "works of the mind" is
limited to the sphere of exchange only and does not touch other
ambits. In the privilege system the book is a commodity insofar as
it satisfies the needs of a buying-selling relationship or a cycle
of such relationships. The reference to Kant's thought here thus
allows for perceiving more clearly where these limits are: the
purchase-and-sale contract regulates only one kind of relationship
to which the book gives rise, that is the relationship that the
publisher establishes with the public by virtue of the contract of
mandate that links the publisher to the author. Neither the
publisher-author relationship, nor the author-public one can turn
purely and simply into a "purchase-and-sale contract".
The transformation of the book-privilege into literary property
(or, better, the move from one paradigm to another), thus has a
clear significance: buying and selling becomes the determining form
for each contract, including the primary and original contract
between the author and the public. This does not mean, in general,
that no other kind of relationship is possible, but these other
relationships will always be "deviant cases" or "exceptional cases"
seeing that they are not provided for in the paradigm.51 What
happens in the move from the privilege to the intellectual property
system is a real change of prospective, as a result of which the
principle of exchange on the basis of sales, which had previously
concerned only one - non-essential - aspect of the author-public
relationship, is now not only central to the relationship but its
totality. Historically, this change began in the 1750's and reached
maturity about a century later.
To show this effect, we could collect some testimony. In the first
half of the 1800's, that is in a crucial period of the rise of the
intellectual property principles in national and supranational
legislation, a wide debate took place in the intellectual world.
Lawyers, men of letters, simple journalists, but above all
economists, were asking about the foundations of the legal
protection of works of the mind and its meaning. Very different
positions emerged that reflect the diversity of interests,
positions, and ideologies.52 Below these differences, however, it is
not difficult to see common responses coming together.
Among the founding fathers of classical economics, one of the
first to concern himself in detail with questions of intellectual
property was John Stuart Mill. In his Principles of Political
Economy, 1848, we read:
It is
generally admitted that the present Patent Laws need much
improvement; but in this case, as well as in the closely analogous
one of Copyright, it would be a gross immorality in the law to set
everybody free to use a person's work without his consent, and
without giving him an equivalent.53
Patent laws and copyright are "analogous cases" but distinct ones
that belong to the family of intellectual property. The important
point, however, is that no result of human work can be used without
asking the permission of the person who has produced it, and without
paying the latter an equivalent. To go against this principle,
according to Mill, is not only unfair but immoral. As we saw
earlier, in the traditional legal conception the payment of an
equivalent is precisely that which cannot take place in the case of
a "work of the mind". To this latter belongs a honorarium, i.e. a
reward that is expressly separate from other kinds of payment (such
as the merces or the pretium) on the grounds that it cannot enclose
any "relationship of equivalence between work and payment".54 What
Mill implicitly assumes, is that the relationship between
"everybody" and the "person's work" is wholly resolved through a
buyer-seller relationship.
This largely implicit assumption in John Stuart Mill becomes
explicit in the work of a contemporary of his, the Italian economist
Gerolamo Boccardo. From the point of view of the history of economic
thought, Boccardo is not at all a "giant" like his English
colleague. His main work, the Dictionary of political economy and
commerce, was published in four volumes between 1857 and 1861, and
is regarded by historians above all as a great explanatory work, a
summa in which are brought together various themes of the liberal
economic culture of the time. Just for this reason, however, it is
interesting for us to read what he says about "Artistic, industrial
and literary property".
The author is a workman in science, civilization, progress, to
whom society pays a salary, just as the factory-owner pays a salary
to his dependants. […] So-called 'literary property' is simply a
wage for work, the price of a work done, the payment for a duty, in
the form of a privilege that the civil law grants to the author in
recognition of his work and service to the social community.55
What
is implicit in Mill's text is stated clearly here. The relationship
between "social community" and the author - a relationship that is
regulated by literary property - is just a particular case of an
economic relationship between a giver and a supplier of work. The
author is just a particular type of "workman", and society treats
the author like a factory-owner treats his employees, by paying a
salary for the work performed. The different nature of the
relationships, which gave rise in the traditional concept to quite
distinct contractual figures, is here flattened to one level - the
"wage for work", "the price of a work done", "payment for duty".
These latter are at last equivalent formulae which are incapable of
any substantial distinction. The author provides a "service" and
society pays a price for it.
We find surprisingly similar words to those of Boccardo in the
work of a very different writer. This is the socialist economist
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, the famous author of the treatise What is
property? In 1858 he published a pamphlet against the legal project
that was intended to make literary property perpetual in France. He
writes:
The
author is a trader, isn't that the truth? And with whom does he
trade? Neither with you, nor with me, nor with someone in
particular; but he trades in general, with the public. […] Between
the author and society there is a tacit agreement, by virtue of
which the author will be paid a fee by means for a temporary
privilege of sale. If there is a great demand for the work the
author will earn a great deal. If the work is refused he will earn
nothing. Let's allow him an agreement that lasts for 30, 40, or 60
years to cover the costs. I say that this contract is perfectly
regular and fair, and that it satisfies all the needs, safeguards
the rights, respects the principles, and responds to all
objections.56
Although coming from different traditions, the two economists arrive
at the same formulations. The contract on the basis of which society
pays the author a straightforward fee is a "perfectly regular and
fair" contract. Proudhon does not and cannot find any objection that
could demonstrate the opposite.
There is therefore an essential difference between the writing
practices in privilege- and intellectual property-system: while in
the first system the relationship author-public can be conceived as
a free liaison between thinking beings - a liaison from which some
reciprocal obligations originate, like the author's responsibility
as regards to the truth, and the public's obligation to truthfully
read -, in the second system, this relationship must, in some way,
be reduced to an "exchange" in which the author's credits are
settled by requiting an equivalent. As a matter of fact, the
"purchase-and-sale contract" is concluded by a payment. Can this
contract really fulfil all the needs? Let's hear, in conclusion, the
words of an American writer. For him, the author is not a "workman"
in society's service nor a "trader". He's rather a "beggar" - and
not in the sense that he's begging for cash:57
Writers, in a way, are like beggars. They are continually begging
for a chance to give of their great gifts - which is the most
heart-rending begging of all and a disgrace to any civilised
community in which it happens. Which is to say, almost the entire
civilised world.58
Notes
1 See generally: M. Woodmansee, "The Genius and the Copyright:
Economic and Legal Conditions of the Emergence of the 'Author'",
Eighteenth Century Studies, 17, 1984 and Id. The Author, Art and the
Market. Rereading the History of Aesthetics, Columbia University
Press, New York 1994; C. Hesse "Enlightenment Epistemology and the
Laws of Authorship in Revolutionary France, 1777-1793",
Representations, n. 30, 1990; M. Rose Authors and Owners. The
Invention of Copyright, Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA-
London 1993; R. Chartier, "Figures of the Author" in: B. Sherman and
A. Strowel (eds.) Of Authors and Origins: Essays in Copyright Laws,
Clarendon Press, Oxford 1994; M. Woodmansee and P. Jaszi (eds.) The
Construction of Authorship: Textual Appropriation in Law and
Literature, Duke University Press, Durham 1994; for the italian
case, see: M. Borghi, La manifattura del pensiero. Diritti d'autore
e mercato delle lettere in Italia (1801-1865), Franco Angeli, Milano
2003.
2 M. Woodmansee "On the Author Effect: Recovering Collectivity",
in M. Woodmansee and P. Jaszi (eds.) The Construction of Authorship,
supra note 1, at 26.
3 Th. Kuhn The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago 1962.
4 In this context we leave out of consideration all the
differences, some of them very relevant, that take place in the
various juridical traditions. Specifically, we shall distinguish
between the Anglo-American copyright system and the
European-continental system of author's rights (cf. W. Fisher
Theories of intellectual property, in S. Munzer (ed.) New Essays in
the Legal and Political Theory of Property, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge MA 2000).
5 "While pre-modern law utilised the language, concepts and
questions of classical jurisprudence, modern intellectual property
law employed the resources of political economy and utilitarianism"
(B. Sherman and L. Bently The Making of Modern Intellectual Property
Law, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge UK 1999, at 4). By
"pre-modern [intellectual property] law", Bently and Sherman refer
to the UK legislation between 1760 and 1850.
6 The term was probably introduced by Jean Baptiste Say
(1767-1832). Other authors, such as Adam Smith (1723-1790), define
the ambit of the fine arts and of thought as "non-productive work'"
while Gian Maria Ortes (1713-1790) speaks of "non economic
occupations" and the Physiocratics of "sterile industries". In the
first half of the 1800's economic theory tried in various ways to
extend economic laws to these areas as well (cf. M. Borghi La
manifattura del pensiero. Diritti d'autore e mercato delle lettere
in Italia (1801-1865), Franco Angeli, Milano 2003, at 55-99).
7 L. Walras, De la propriété intellectuelle, in "Gazette de
Lausanne", 10, 11, 12 June 1890.
8 Ibidem, at 58.
9 This principle had already been formulated some years earlier by
Antonio Scialoja in his book on economics (cf. A. Scialoja Principii
della economia sociale esposti in ordine ideologico, Torino, 1846,
at 22).
10 The term "fiction" is used here in a strict technical sense,
not in a "moral" one (see generally the theory of "fictitious
commodities" in: K. Polanyi The Great Transformation, New York
1944).
11 Quoted in J. Boncompain La Révolution des auteurs. Naissance de
la propriété intellectuelle (1773-1815), Fayard, Paris 2001, at 16
(my italics). It should be remembered that author's rights are now
included in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights of 1948.
12 The most significant dates in this development are 1883 and
1886, where internationals agreements respectively on patents and on
copyright were reached in the "Great Conventions" of Paris and
Berne, which sanction the bifurcation of the intellectual property
rights into two distinct branches (cf. J.H. Reichmann Legal Hybrids
between the Patent and Copyright Paradigm, "Columbia Law Review", n.
94, 1994).
13 The treatise debates openly against the indiscriminate use of
the language of 'creation' to define the work of the artist. "Do you
want to know what the artist really does? I say, that he invents
[…]. I ask you to use this word instead of that harmful expression
'to create'". (A. Manzoni Dell'invenzione. Dialogo, in Tutte le
opere, a cura di A. Chiari e F. Ghisalberti, vol. III, Mondadori,
Milano 1863, at 694).
14 Ludwig Gieseke, observing the use of the Latin term invenire
(germ. erfinden) in German privileges in the 1600's, writes that
"the concept of invention includes an ambit of indefinite activity
that is extended from the mere construction of something to the
creation of genius" (L. Gieseke Die geschichtliche Entwicklung des
deutschen Urheberrechts, Verlag Otto Schwartz, Göttingen, 1957, at
37). Speaking of an "indefinite ambit", Gieseke retrospectively
applies to the privilege system a distinction - between "invention"
and "creation" - that belongs only to the intellectual
property-system.
15 Commenting on one of the first French privileges, granted by
Louis XII to the writer Eloi d'Amerval in 1508, Elizabeth Armstrong
says: "The economic considerations which Eloi had put forward were
to remain uppermost in most request for privileges, whether by
authors or publishers." (E. Armstrong Before Copyright. The French
Book-Privilege System 1498-1526, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge UK 1990, at 79, 84). She writes later: "Publishers who
sought privilege naturally tended to put forward economic arguments
in support of their request […] Sometimes however the difficulty and
cost of acquiring the manuscript is particularly stressed." (Ibid.,
at 84). The high costs of production (for paper, characters, for the
purchase of the manuscript, etc.) were frequently mentioned in
Venetian privileges (cf. R. Fulin Documenti per servire alla storia
della tipografia veneziana, "Archivio veneto", XXIII, 1882).
16 E. Armstrong Before Copyright, supra note 16, at 78.
17 M. Infelise L'editoria veneziana nel 700, Franco Angeli, Milano
1991, at 289.
18 M. Rose Authors and Owners. The Invention of Copyright, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge MA - London 1993, at 11.
19 Lodovica Braida quotes the evidence of Giuseppe Vernazza, the
author in 1812 of a history of 18th century publishing in Turin (L.
Braida Il commercio delle idee. Editoria e circolazione del libro
nella Torino del Settecento, Olschki, Firenze 1995, at 336-7). The
evidence is confirmed by the collections of Savoy privileges in the
1700's (L. C. Ubertazzi I Savoia e gli autori, Giuffré, Milano 2000,
at 131 sg.)
20 The cases revealed by Elizabeth Armsrong confirm this
hypothesis: "On the available evidence, the choice of books granted
the longer duration shows signs of being rational rather than
capricious" (E. Armstrong Before Copyright, supra note 16, at 122).
21 G. B. Salvioni, L'arte della stampa nel Veneto. La proprietà
letteraria, "Giornale degli economisti di Padova", IV, 1877, at 261.
22 J. Feather From Rights in Copies to Copyright: The Recognition
of Author's Rights in English Law and Practice in the Sixteenth and
Seventeenth Century, in M. Woodmansee and P. Jaszi (eds.) The
Construction of Authorship, supra note 1, at 193.
23 L. C. Ubertazzi I Savoia e gli autori, supra note 20, at 19.
"The literary privileges of the 18th century in Savoy are still very
similar to booksellers' mercantile privileges" (ibidem, at 20).
24 M. Rose Authors and Owners, supra, note 19, at 17. Later we
shall see why the honorarium is the suitable method for remunerating
the author.
25 G. B. Salvioni L'arte della stampa nel Veneto, supra note 22,
at 259. The provision was confirmed in the law on printing of 1603.
In the judgement in the case Pezzana e Consorti (1781) concerning
the perpetuity of privileges, the court wrote that "the privilege
gives the publisher the necessary security of capital invested in
view of the profit" (ibidem, at 264).
26 E. Armstrong Before Copyright, supra note 16, at 21-62.
27 R. Fulin Documenti, supra note 16, at 93.
28 L. Gieseke Die geschichtiliche Entwicklung, supra note 15, at
24-37.
29 This refers, clearly, to Catholic and imperial "universality"
which remained more or less in vigour until the end of the 1700's.
30
This no-coincidence was for instance the case of Italy until 1861
and of Germany until 1871.
31 L. Febvre and H.-J. Martin L'apparition du livre, Ed. Albin
Michel, Paris 1958, at 308.
32 In Germany the Jesuits were authorised by the emperor to give
special privileges (cf. N. Stolfi La proprietà intellettuale, vol.
I, Utet, Torino 1915, at 62).
33 The general extension of privileges in the course of the 1800's
is an important sign of the collapse of the privilege system. In
1780, the Venetian government established the perpetuity of
privileges in order to deal with the grave publishing crisis in the
area (G. B. Salvioni L'arte della stampa nel Veneto, supra note 22,
at 210-12). In this way the exchange value of the book (and thus its
status as commodity) was extended infinitely, beyond its natural
economic cycle. This provision looks similar to that of a government
that tries to cope with a stagnant housing market by declaring a
permanent opening (24/7) of the Stock Exchange…
34 I. Kant Metaphysik der Sitten, in Kants gesammelte Schriften,
ed. Königl. Preuß. Akademie der Wissenschaft, De Gruyter,
Berlin-Leipzig 1907 [hereinafter KGS], Bd. 6, at 404.
35 I. Kant Von der Unrechtmäßigkeit der Büchernachdrucks, KGS, Bd.
7.
36 One can certainly imagine other derived relationships, adding
further subjects (the distributor, the bookseller, the translator,
etc.). The substance, however, would remain the same. Every other
relationship would become part of one of the three mentioned
contractual figures.
37 Cf. A. Berger Encyclopedic Dictionary of Roman Law,
Philadelphia 1953.
38 One can read, in the J.-H. Zedler's Universal-Lexicon (1735):
"Honorarium means acknowledgement or reward, recognition, favor,
stipend; it is not in proportion to or equivalent to the services
performed; differs from pay or wages, which are specifically
determined by contracting parties and which express a relationship
of equivalence between work and payment" (quoted in: M. Woodmansee
The Author, Art and the Market, supra note 1, at 42).
39 I. Kant Von der Unrechtmäßigkeit der Büchernachdrucks, KGS, Bd.
7.
40 I. Kant Metaphysik der Sitten, KGS, Bd. 6, at 401.
41 Ibidem, at 400.
42 I. Kant Was heißt, sich im Denken orientieren?, KGS, Bd. 7, at
144-5.
43 Cf. I. Kant Kritik der reinen Vernunft: "we can reduce all acts
of the understanding to judgements, so that understanding may be
represented as the faculty of judging. For it is, according to what
has been said above, a faculty of thought." (A 69, B 84). Judging
means connecting a predicate to a subject in the form "S is P". The
truth of thought corresponds to the correctness of the judgement.
(On these questions, which cannot be explored more deeply here, see
generally M. Heidegger Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik, 1929,
hrsg. Fr.-W. von Herrmann, Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 3, Klostermann,
Frankfurt a./M. 1991 and Id. Einleitung in die Philosophie, 1928/29,
hrsg. O. Saame und I. Saame-Speidel, Gesamtausgabe, Bd. 27,
Klostermann, Frankfurt a./M. 1996, at 267 fw.).
44 The concept of such unity is the "category". The ways of
"connecting", i.e. of unifying, are deduced from the traditional
table of judgements (Kritik der reinen Vernunft, A 65, B 80 fw.).
45 I. Kant Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht, KGS, Bd. 7. at
128-9.
46 "If there was an initial lack of perception of the fact that
the judgement of the land-surveyor regularly agreed with the
judgement of all those working diligently and carefully in the same
area, mathematics itself would not be able to be free from the fear
of falling into error" (ibidem, at 129).
47 Cf. "the truth shall make you free" (John 7:32).
48 I. Kant Grundlegung der Metaphysik der Sitten, KGS, Bd. 4.
49 Ibidem.
50 V. Alfieri Del principe e delle lettere, a cura di E. Falcomer,
Rizzoli, Milano 1986 at 212.
51
See J.H. Reichmann Legal Hybrids, supra note 13.
52 See generally: F. Machlup and E. Penrose "The Patent
Controversy in the Nineteenth Century", Journal of Economic History,
1, 1950; P. Drahos A Philosophy of Intellectual Property Law,
Dartmouth, Aldershot 1996; B. Sherman and L. Bently The Making of
Modern Intellectual Property Law, supra note 6, at 101 fw..; M.
Borghi La manifattura del pensiero, supra note 1, at 55-99.
53 J. S. Mill Principles of Political Economy (1848), Book V,
chap. X.
54 M. Woodmansee The Author, Art and the Market, supra note 1, at
42 (see also supra note 39).
55 G. Boccardo Dizionario della economia sociale e del commercio,
vol. IV, Torino 1861.
56 P.-J. Proudhon Les majorats littéraires. Examen d'un projet de
loi, in Oeuvres complètes, tome XVI, Paris 1868, at 24.
57 See supra the Miller's quotation in exergue.
58 H. Miller Stand Still Like the Hummingbird, New York 1962, at
75.
|